Skip to main content

Home/ Groups/ Science Technology Society
Todd Suomela

The Technium: Reasons to Diminish Technology - 0 views

  •  
    Arguments against technology: contrary to nature, to humans, to technology itself (self-destruction), to God.
Todd Suomela

On Being a Scientist: Third Edition - 0 views

  •  
    The scientific research enterprise is built on a foundation of trust. Scientists trust that the results reported by others are valid. Society trusts that the results of research reflect an honest attempt by scientists to describe the world accurately and without bias. But this trust will endure only if the scientific community devotes itself to exemplifying and transmitting the values associated with ethical scientific conduct.
Todd Suomela

Rands In Repose: The Makers of Things - 0 views

  •  
    musings on Brooklyn Bridge.
Todd Suomela

Rationally Speaking: Could it be? Science critics calls for a truce - 0 views

  •  
    reaction to Harry Collins article in Nature "We cannot live by skepticism alone"
Todd Suomela

Strange Horizons Reviews: The Shock of the Old by David Edgerton, reviewed by Bruce Ste... - 0 views

  •  
    Edgerton's major line of attack is the assertion that we falsely imagine that "technology" is the same as "innovation" and "invention." That the vast bulk of "technology" is the installed base. The old stuff.
Todd Suomela

Just Another Deisidaimon - 0 views

  •  
    Philosophy of rationality much more than sociology of knowledge.
Todd Suomela

Hello, Darkness - 96.03 - 0 views

  • But the implication of electricity in the sleep deficit seems hard to argue with. Whatever it is that we wish or are made to do--pursue leisure, earn a living--there are simply far more usable hours now in which to do it
  • In the United States at midnight more than five million people are at work at full-time jobs. Supermarkets, gas stations, copy shops--many of these never close.
  • Living with electric lights makes it difficult to retrieve the experience of a non-electrified society. For all but the very wealthy, who could afford exorbitant arrays of expensive artificial lights, nightfall brought the works of daytime to a definitive end. Activities that need good light--where sharp tools are wielded or sharply defined boundaries maintained; purposeful activities designed to achieve specific goals; in short, that which we call work--all this subsided in the dim light of evening. Absent the press of work, people typically took themselves safely to home and were left with time in the evening for less urgent and more sensual matters: storytelling, sex, prayer, sleep, dreaming.
  • ...1 more annotation...
  • John Staudenmaier, a historian of technology and a Jesuit priest, for a recent conference at MIT. (The essay will appear in a book called The Idea of Progress Revisited, edited by Leo Marx and Bruce Mazlish.) Staudenmaier makes the point--obvious when brought up, though we've mostly lost sight of it--that from the time of the hominid Lucy, in Hadar, Ethiopia, to the time of Thomas Edison, in West Orange, New Jersey, the onset of darkness sharply curtailed most kinds of activity for most of our ancestors.
  •  
    Speculative connections between electric lighting, sleep deficits, and health.
  •  
    I wonder if the driving force behind the sleep deficit is in fact more pervasive, and indeed global in nature: the triumph of light.
Todd Suomela

Rationally Speaking: The very foundations of science - 0 views

  • The first way to think about probability is as a measure of the frequency of an event: if I say that the probability of a coin to land heads up is 50% I may mean that, if I flip the coin say 100 times, on average I will get heads 50 times. This is not going to get us out of Hume’s problem, because probabilities interpreted as frequencies of events are, again, a form of induction
  • Secondly, we can think of probabilities as reflecting subjective judgment. If I say that it is probable that the coin will land heads up, I might simply be trying to express my feeling that this will be the case. You might have a different feeling, and respond that you don’t think it's probable that the coin will lend heads up. This is certainly not a viable solution to the problem of induction, because subjective probabilities are, well, subjective, and hence reflect opinions, not degrees of truth.
  • Lastly, one can adopt what Okasha calls the logical interpretation of probabilities, according to which there is a probability X that an event will occur means that we have objective reasons to believe (or not) that X will occur (for instance, because we understand the physics of the solar system, the mechanics of cars, or the physics of coin flipping). This doesn’t mean that we will always be correct, but it does offer a promising way out of Hume’s dilemma, since it seems to ground our judgments on a more solid foundation. Indeed, this is the option adopted by many philosophers, and would be the one probably preferred by scientists, if they ever gave this sort of thing a moment’s thought.
  •  
    short summary of some probabilistic responses to the problem of induction
Todd Suomela

IPY 2007-2008 - 0 views

  •  
    IPY = International Polar Year, concluding statement
Todd Suomela

The Technium: Many Species, One Mind - 0 views

  •  
    Do we remain one species, or diverge into many? Do we remain of many minds, or merge into one?
Todd Suomela

Scientific Explanation (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) - 0 views

  •  
    Reviews deductive-nomological (Popper, Hempel); statistical relevance (Salmon); causal mechanical; and unificationist (Friedman and Kitcher
Todd Suomela

Winner of the 2008 Lakatos Award announced - News - Press and Information Office - LSE - 0 views

  •  
    Richard Healey (University of Arizona), for his book Gauging What's Real: the conceptual foundations of contemporary gauge theories
« First ‹ Previous 481 - 500 of 595 Next › Last »
Showing 20 items per page